Part of the Politics series on |
Youth rights |
Activities
- Bailey v. Drexel Furniture Co.
- Child Labor Deterrence Act
- Children's Online Privacy Protection Act
- Convention on the Rights of the Child
- Fair Labor Standards Act
- Hammer v. Dagenhart
- History of youth rights in the United States
- Morse v. Frederick
- Newsboys' strike of 1899
- Quebec Charter of Human Rights and Freedoms
- Wild in the Streets
|
Theory/Concepts
- Adultcentrism
- Adultism
- Ageism
- Criminalization
- Democracy
- Ephebiphobia
- Fear of children
- Fear of youth
- Intergenerational equity
- Paternalism
- Social class
- Suffrage
- Taking Children Seriously
- Universal suffrage
- Unschooling
- Youth activism
- Youth suffrage
- Youth voice
|
Issues
- Age of candidacy
- Age of consent
- Age of majority
- Article 12 in Scotland
- Behavior modification facility
- Child labour
- Compulsory education
- Conscription
- Corporal punishment
- Curfew
- Child abuse
- Emancipation of minors
- Gambling age
- Homeschooling
- Human rights and youth sport
- In loco parentis
- Juvenile delinquency
- Juvenile court
- Legal drinking age
- Legal working age
- Minimum driving age
- Marriageable age
- Minor (law)
- Minors and abortion
- School leaving age
- Smoking age
- Status offense
- Underage drinking in America
- Voting age
- Youth-adult partnership
- Youth participation
- Youth politics
- Youth voting
|
Organizations
- Americans for a Society Free from Age Restrictions
- Human Rights and Youth Rights Commission
- National Youth Rights Association
- One World Youth Project
- Queer Youth Network
- Students for a Democratic Society
- Freechild Project
- Three O'Clock Lobby
- YouthKiAwaaz.com
- Youth International Party
- Youth Liberation of Ann Arbor
- Young Communist League of Canada
|
Persons
- Adam Fletcher (activist)
- David J. Hanson
- David Joseph Henry
- John Caldwell Holt
- Alex Koroknay-Palicz
- Lyn Duff
- Mike A. Males
- Neil Postman
- Sonia Yaco
|
Related
- Animal rights
- Anti-racism
- Direct democracy
- Egalitarianism
- Feminism
- Libertarianism
- Socialism
- Students rights
|
- Youth Rights
- Social movements portal
|
|
Paternalism (or parentalism) is behavior, by a person, organization or state, which limits some person or group's liberty or autonomy for what is presumed to be that person's or group's own good.[1] Paternalism can also imply that the behavior is against or regardless of the will of a person, or also that the behavior expresses an attitude of superiority.[2]
The word paternalism is from the Greek pater (πάτηρ, πατέρας) for father, though paternalism should be distinguished from patriarchy. Some, such as John Stuart Mill, think paternalism to be appropriate towards children: "It is, perhaps, hardly necessary to say that this doctrine is meant to apply only to human beings in the maturity of their faculties. We are not speaking of children, or of young persons below the age which the law may fix as that of manhood or womanhood."[3] Paternalism towards adults is sometimes thought to treat them as if they were children.[4]
Contents
- 1 Examples
- 2 Soft and hard paternalism
- 3 Criteria for effective paternalism
- 4 Opponents of paternalism
- 5 See also
- 6 References
- 7 External links
Examples
Examples of paternalism include laws requiring the use of motorcycle helmets, laws punishing citizens for not obtaining their driving license in time (see driving licence in Belgium), a parent forbidding their children to engage in dangerous activities, and a psychiatrist confiscating sharp objects from someone who is suicidally depressed.
Soft and hard paternalism
The terms soft and hard are used in two quite different senses in this context. Philosophers, following Joel Feinberg's influential book Harm to Self (1986), usually use "soft paternalism" for paternalism towards a person whose action or choice is insufficiently voluntary to be genuinely his or hers. Hard paternalism in this usage means paternalism towards a person whose action or choice is sufficiently voluntary to be genuinely his or hers. Soft paternalism in this usage may also refer to interference with a person aimed to establish whether or not his or her action or choice is sufficiently voluntary. In contrast, economists and lawyers usually use "soft paternalism" for mild paternalism, that is paternalism that is not coercive, or not very "heavy-handed". For example, libertarian paternalism is soft paternalism in this sense. Hard paternalism in this usage is coercive paternalism.
Criteria for effective paternalism
Thomas Pogge argues that there are a number of criteria for paternalism.[5]
- The concept should work within human flourishing. Generally accepted items such as nutrition, clothing, shelter, certain basic freedoms may be acceptable by a range of religious and social backgrounds.
- The criteria should be "modest".[further explanation needed]
- The requirements of the criteria should not be understood as exhaustive; leaving societies the ability to modify the criteria based on their own needs.
- The supplementary considerations introduced by such more ambitious criteria of justice must not be allowed to outweigh the modest considerations.[further explanation needed]
Opponents of paternalism
See also: Social engineering (political science) and Nanny state
In his Two Treatises of Government, John Locke argues (against Robert Filmer) that political and paternal power cannot be identified. Mill opposes state paternalism on the grounds that individuals know their own good better than the state does, that the moral equality of persons demands respect for others' liberty, and that paternalism disrupts the development of an independent character. In On Liberty he writes:
...the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own good, either physical or moral, is not a sufficient warrant. He cannot rightfully be compelled to do or forbear because it will be better for him to do so, because it will make him happier, because, in the opinion of others, to do so would be wise, or even right.[3]:14
Contemporary opponents of paternalism often appeal to the ideal of personal autonomy.
See also
- Adultism
- Obscurantism
- Soft paternalism
- Industrial paternalism
- Rule according to higher law
References
- ^ Dworkin, Gerald, "Paternalism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2010 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.)
- ^ Shiffrin, Seana. 2000. Paternalism, Unconscionability Doctrine, and Accommodation. Philosophy and Public Affairs 29(3): 205-250.
- ^ a b Mill, J.S. [1859]/(1991) "On Liberty", published in Gray, John (ed), John Stuart Mill: On Liberty and Other Essays, Oxford: Oxford University Press
- ^ Feinberg, Joel. 1986. Harm to Self. Oxford: Oxford University Press. P. 4
- ^ Pogge, Thomas (2008). World poverty and human rights (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Polity. ISBN 978-0-7456-4143-0. Retrieved 9 March 2015.
External links
- Paternalism, by Peter Suber. From Philosophy of Law: An Encyclopedia, edited by Christopher Berry Gray, Garland Pub. Co., 1999, vol. II, pp. 632–635.
- Paternalism, by Gerald Dworkin. From The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Counting the Dragon's Teeth and Claws: The Definition of Hard Paternalism by Thaddeus Mason Pope. From 20 Georgia State University Law Review 659-722 (2004)
- Monstrous Impersonation: A Critique of Consent-Based Justifications for Hard Paternalism by Thaddeus Mason Pope. From 73 UMKC Law Review 681-713 (2005)
- Is Public Health Paternalism Really Never Justified? A Response to Joel Feinberg by Thaddeus Mason Pope. From 30 Oklahoma City University Law Review 121-207 (2005)